칼 마르크스(좌파)를 향한 교회의 올바른 비평 제안 - 『자본론』에 관한 영상 & 논문 첨부
하나님과 이웃과 개혁신학을 사랑합니다.

하나님은 사랑이시라 사랑 안에 거하는 자는 하나님 안에 거하고 하나님도 그의 안에 거하시느니라(요일 4:16)

후원과 광고협찬을 부탁드려요! 자세히보기

신학 자료/철학 & 과학 & 인문학 & 예술

칼 마르크스(좌파)를 향한 교회의 올바른 비평 제안 - 『자본론』에 관한 영상 & 논문 첨부

개혁신학어벤져스 2022. 10. 11. 23:55

 현대 그리스도인들에게 '마르크스'는 아주 중요한 인물입니다.

 거의 북한을 제외하고 세상의 대부분 나라에서 자본주의(케인즈 학파)가 주류를 이루는데요! 마르크스는 케인즈 직전 근대 신학(특히, 자본주의와 자유경제주의를 바탕으로 한 영광의 신학)이 나아가야 할 큰 방향성에 대한 답을 요구한 인물입니다. 곧, 마르크스는당시  '자본주의 또는 자유경제주의의 문제'를 지적하며, 해당 사회에 살고 있는 그리스도인들에게 어떻게 신앙인으로서 해당 체제를 대해야 할지를 질문합니다.

 * 이렇게 마르크스를 접근하는 방식이 가장 그리스도인들에게 생산적인 접근법입니다.

 

 실로,  마르크스에 대한 체계적인 논의는 '철학적으로나 사회경제적 흐름 속'에서 '공산주의(또는 좌파?!)의 정립 배경'에 대해 바르게 이해하고 비평하도록 합니다. 특히, '공산주의(소위, 좌파)'라는 개념은 현재 한국에서 그리스도인들에게 다루어져야 마땅한데, 이는 자본에 의해 인격이 짓밟히는 상황이 현재 진행형으로 발생하기 때문이고, 북한이라는 공산주의 국가를 한민족으로 또한 동시에 적국으로 두고 있기 때문입니다.

 

 * 관련하여, 헤겔의 정반합 개념에 유물론적 전제를 도입한 방법론은 어찌보면, 자본주의가 강화되는 과정에서 당연히 발생하게 된, 곧, 마르크스가 아니더라도 사회적 문제를 직시한 누군가 지적할 수 밖에 없었던 자연스러운 역사적 흐름에 의합니다. 즉, 단순히 또는 막연히 마르크스와 공산주의(소위, 좌파 포함)가 싫다는,,, 그리고 이를 바탕으로 자본주의나 민주주의에 민족주의(1, 2차 세계대전 이후 강조된)를 주입하여, 잘못된 정치행위를 적극적으로 벌이는 그리스도인(정말로 신앙이 있는지 모르겠으나)이 되지 않아야 합니다.

 

 -> 마르크스에 관해 살펴볼 수 있는 쉽고 정확한 다큐를 링크합니다. 개혁교회 그리스도인으로서 마르크스의 한계와 공산주의의 위험성을 하나님 중심적으로 이해하길 소원합니다. 그리고 마르크스도 결국은 '칼빈'의 후예 중 하나입니다. 다시 말해, 마르크스는 기존의 영국을 포함한 유럽의 각종 사회, 문화, 철학, 경제에 대한 세계관에서 '자유'와 '평등'을 강조하고 실천하려 한 인물입니다. 핵심적으로 제 2의 마르크스는 자본주의 또는 자유경제주의 세계에서 언제든 배출될 수 있습니다.

 

 -> 마르크스를 개혁신학적으로 적절히 비판한 한국어 영상은 찾지 못했습니다. 관련하여, 19세기 사회의 주류 경제학과 철학을 혼합적으로 취사선택한 '애매한 포지션'으로 을 신학적으로 세세하게 비판하는 일은 매우 불필요합니다.

 

 * 가장 아래에 그리스도인으로서 마르크스에 대해 올바로 접근&대처할 수 있는 좋은 논문을 첨부(PDF, HTML)합니다.


 * 인류에 가장 큰 영향을 끼친 책, 칼 마르크스의 『자본론』 | 역사를 바꾼 사상가 칼 마르크스가 꿈꾸었던 세상

https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1ugANq0ZULg 


 * 마르크스 자본론 핵심 살펴보기 | 홍익대 경영대학 홍기훈 교수

https://youtu.be/cErmS036LOU?si=AYEA5biJyfRqgCF-


A Critique of Karl Marx on Religion_ Historical Instances of the.pdf
0.35MB

 

Claremont Colleges  
Fall 2020  
A Critique of Karl Marx on Religion: Historical Instances of the  
Church and Revolution  
Jake Steedman  
Claremont Graduate University  
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cgu_etd  
Recommended Citation  
Steedman, Jake. (2020). A Critique of Karl Marx on Religion: Historical Instances of the Church and  
Revolution. CGU Theses & Dissertations, 297. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cgu_etd/297.  
This Open Access Master's Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the CGU Student Scholarship at  
Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in CGU Theses & Dissertations by an authorized  
administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact scholarship@cuc.claremont.edu.  
A Critique of Karl Marx on Religion: Historical Instances of the Church and Revolution  
Jake Steedman  
Claremonet Graduate University  
Master’s Thesis  
2020  
Presented to the Graduate Faculty of Claremont Graduate University in partial  
fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Religion. We certify  
thatwe have read this document and approve it as adequate in scope and quality for the  
degree of Master of Arts.  
Dr. Kevin Wolfe  
1
Table of Contents  
Introduction……1  
Part I……………3  
Part II…………..23  
Conclusion…….46  
i
Introduction  
Marx was a man deeply entrenched in the concrete realities of human activity.  
His radical engagement with grassroots political movements distinguishes him from  
other historically acclaimed philosophers. Both a fastidious student of Hegel and an  
outspoken, prolific journalist, Marx’s thought was uniquely placed at the center of social  
movements.1  
It is perhaps this unique quality of Marx that has made him a pointedly polarizing  
figure, both now and during his time in the middle to late 19th century. Having radical  
ideas was not outside the norm of philosophical discourse. But, Marx’s ideas and  
professional experiences mobilized and instigated social change and revolution,  
threatening political and religious establishments. The reason Marx’s name carries such  
poignant connotation in modern America is in part the same reason he was expelled  
from Paris in 1845. It is also on these grounds that a careful study of Marx is a worthy  
endeavor.  
While there are many places to explore nuance in Marxist thought, focusing on  
his claims on religion is vital. In academic circles Marx’s contributions to philosophy are  
typically associated with novel ideas on labor, alienation, and capital. However, religion  
in Marx is a major skeletal aspect to his work at large, which is evident from the outset  
of his life’s project. In one of his earliest and most cited writings, he claims that criticism  
1 Jon Elster, An Introduction to Karl Marx, (Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1986), 6  
2 Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of the Right, introduction, trans., Joseph O'Malley, transcribed,  
Andy Blunden (Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1970). “Criticism” a term couched in German  
Philosophy can be understood as an examination against the limitations of human reason. For Marx, this  
notion may convey the severity in which “religion” can hold against the progress of human reason and  
human social progress.  
3 Ibid.  
4 David Leopold, The Young Karl Marx, (Cambridge University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007), 23 - 27  
5 ibid  
6 Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, introduction. “If therefore, instead of the oeuvres  
incomplete of our real history, we criticize the oeuvres posthumes of our ideal history, philosophy, our  
1
criticism is in the midst of the questions of which the present says:
that is the question
. What, in  
of religion is a “prerequisite to all criticism.”2 Uncovering the core of Marx’s critique of  
religion sheds light on the entirety of Marx’s writings.  
Furthermore, an investigation into Marx’s thought on religion will bring clarity to  
his ideas, which have been obfuscated on account of the polemical thread with which  
he has been associated. In many cases, Marxism is equated with atheism, and atheism  
is equated with a host of political connotations. “Religion is the opium of the people” is  
one of the most frequently used lines to against religious belief.3 At its face-value, this  
line suggests people use religion to medicate themselves artificially--forfeiting a true  
view of the world in order to bring themselves into solace and hope. Yet, there is a  
much more complex story to be told around these ideas.  
A careful study will show a much more complex understanding of Marx’s view on  
religion. Furthermore, a careful study of religious movements following Marx will show a  
more complimentary relationship between these movements and religion than both  
Marx and conservative religious practitioners would suggest. Altogether, this paper will  
seek, generally, to show that Marx’s ideas on religion and social change are not  
diametrically opposed, but in fact, in many respects, complementary. I will seek to more  
fully explicate a dialectical understanding of Marx’s view on religion, and demonstrate  
through historical examples, that social change and process is not impeded by religion,  
but rather they act as catalysts and energizers of change.  
2 Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of the Right, introduction, trans., Joseph O'Malley, transcribed,  
Andy Blunden (Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1970). “Criticism” a term couched in German  
Philosophy can be understood as an examination against the limitations of human reason. For Marx, this  
notion may convey the severity in which “religion” can hold against the progress of human reason and  
human social progress.  
3 Ibid.  
2
Part 1  
Contextualizing Marx’s work is important, as is the case for any philosopher who  
ultimately responds to their predecessors. However, Marx as both a political activist and  
philosopher was responding to both the global geopolitical circumstances of his time,  
and the philosophical milieu. For now, we’ll turn to the political circumstances.  
There is a peculiar aspect to Marx’s engagement with the political circumstances  
in Germany. Namely, Marx was quite focused on a critique of the modern state, despite  
Germany lagging behind in its own formation of such a state.4 Marx saw Germany as  
politically underdeveloped compared to the rest of the modern world, while at the same  
time, still participating in sophisticated philosophical discourse.5 While Germany was  
practically lagging behind, it was ideally setting the global pace in philosophical  
conversations. In the introduction to The Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy or Right, Marx  
explicates this peculiar dynamic in an effort to secure a foundation from which to  
articulate a criticism against the modern (ideal) state.6  
In The Critique Marx defines the modern state by a few central tenets.7 The first  
of these tenets is that the modern state consists of a clear separation between “civil”  
and “political life.”8 To more fully explain this relationship, Marx elaborates at length how  
this separation is a departure from previous eras’ relationships, where political and civil  
life were unified. He claims “The whole existence of the medieval classes was political;  
4 David Leopold, The Young Karl Marx, (Cambridge University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007), 23 - 27  
5 ibid  
6 Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, introduction. “If therefore, instead of the oeuvres  
incomplete of our real history, we criticize the oeuvres posthumes of our ideal history, philosophy, our  
criticism is in the midst of the questions of which the present says: that is the question. What, in  
progressive nations, is a practical break with modern state conditions, is, in Germany, where even those  
conditions do not yet exist, at first a critical break with the philosophical reflexion of those conditions”  
7 Leopold, 60 - 80  
8 ibid, par 303  
3
their existence was the existence of the state. Their legislative activity, their grant of  
taxes for the realm was merely a particular issue of their universal political significance  
and efficacy. Their class was their state.”9 Put in Hegelian terms, the particular (civil)  
individuals comprising the universal state (political) were only distinguishable by  
function, and not by motivating cause. That function’s purpose was solely directed  
toward the state, and not to individuals themselves.  
According to Marx, this separation was first completely realized in The French  
Revolution, because at that time, civil classes and political classes were fully distinct,  
and--as is quite evident in this example--”antithetical”. This brings to the fore the second  
tenet, of Marx’s conception of the modern state. On this point Marx claims that not only  
were the political and civil classes separated by their principle and motivation, they were  
opposed and contrary to one another. Marx attributes “particular interests” to individuals  
of civil society, and a “universal interest” of the state. Where those interests were  
conflated in the middle ages, were now conflicting in the modern state.10  
The philosophical context in which Marx writes is also equally crucial to fully and  
completely understand how he perceives religion within his larger system. While Marx  
was responding to several philosophers throughout the development of his work,  
commentators on religion were a central point of focus.11 Bruno Bauer, Ludwig  
Feauerbach, and Georg Hegel are the three which will be a point of focus with regard to  
Marx’s thought on religion.  
9 ibid  
10 Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, par 280, 281  
11 Other Young Hegelians in which Marx concerned himself with include Strauss, Ruge, Hess and Striner  
4
The relationship between Marx and Hegel has been regarded as “one of the  
most challenging problems in the history of thought.”12 In all the continuity shared by  
Hegel and Marx, their pronounced divergence on the role of God may trump the entirety  
of that continuity. The reason for this being that for Hegel, God is where his system  
begins and ends. For Marx, the abolishment of God is also, in many respects the  
beginning and end of his thought. Hegel writes in Science of Logic, “As [pure] science,  
truth is pure self-consciousness as it develops itself and has the shape of the self, so  
that that which exists in and for itself is the conscious concept and the concept as such  
is that which exists in and for itself.”13 For Hegel, logic and truth is that which is simply  
“absolute form itself.” And he continues, that “It can therefore be said that this content is  
the exposition of God as he is in his eternal essence before the creation of nature and  
of a finite spirit.”14 For Hegel, God is the developing Spirit of the universe which  
becomes realized by particular minds which conceive of God. The meta-process of  
sublation finds it’s ultimate reality in the mind of God, which is itself pure self-  
consciousness.15  
Hegel’s work, especially in The Phenomenology is, to the least, a dense and  
speculative one that outlines the holistic metaphysical reality. It is no surprise then that  
God is the epicenter in that process, which is a description about the universe and  
about consciousness and particular consciousnesses. Religion and God for Hegel stops  
well short of any justified practical theology--or rather, the concrete activities of  
12 Sidney Hook, From Hegel to Marx, Humanities Press: New York, NY, 1950), 13  
13 Georg Hegel, Science of Logic, Science of Logic. Found in Lenin’s Collected Works. 4th  
Edition. Volume 38. Trans. Clemence Dutt, Ed. Stewart Smith, (Progress Publishers: Moscow, RU, 1976),  
21.34  
14 Ibid  
15 “Sublation” being the process commonly called “abolish,” “preserve,” transcende,” is the signature mark  
of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit.  
5
organized religion. Hegel’s comments on God can be summarized in this excerpt from  
The Phenomenology: “God is solely attainable in pure speculative knowledge, he is only  
within that knowledge, and he is merely that knowledge itself, for he is spirit, and this  
speculative knowledge is revealed religion’s knowledge.”16 It is on such speculative  
grounds that Marx makes his dramatic and immediate departure from Hegel.  
But even while Marx makes such a dramatic opposition to Hegel’s central tenets,  
there is a peculiar shared discourse, which allows Marx to converse with Hegel’s  
writings with a formidable intelligibility. Marx and Hegel may have been on different  
planets, but they were making paralleled observations about the heavens, so to speak.  
The radical departure from the two thinkers on the subject comes down to the central  
place God plays in the development and ends of human history. For Hegel, God is  
imminently manifest in the idea of reason. That one can reason presupposes an  
unconditioned reality (God) that exists irrespective of the subjective observer of God.17  
And, what Hegel considers “fulfillment of history” is the activity of moving back and  
through God, which is pure freedom. As Sidney Hook simply states, “History [for Hegel]  
is the autobiography of God.”18 With that said, Hegel certainly connotes a deterministic  
aspect to history as found in God. As he claims,  
With this explanation, Divine Providence may be said to stand to  
the world and its process in the capacity of absolute cunning. God  
lets men do as they please with their particular passions and  
interests; but the result is the accomplishment of-not their plans, but  
his, and these differ decidedly from the ends primarily sought by  
those whom he employs19  
16 Georg Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit (1807), trans. J.B. Bailie, (Harper and Row: New York, NY,  
1910)  
17 Ibid.  
18 Sidney Hook, From Hegel to Marx; studies in the intellectual development of Karl Marx, (Humanities  
Press: New York, NY), 1950, 36.  
19 Hegel, Science of Logic, Par 209  
6
The heart of Hegel’s conception of history--his formulation of divine providence--is  
where we find Marx vehemently at odds with Hegel.  
Historical development and process is the jargon shared by Hegel and Marx, but  
the source and catalyst of this movement are at stark contrast. Marx, like Hegel, does  
believe history is formed and developed in a systematic and directional way, but that  
movement is centered on the heart and will of society. The base needs and humans  
and the desire to live and flourish has brought about revolution and property  
redistribution et al. God is not simply uninvolved in this order but is the ultimate  
distraction to historical development and progress. Which is why he plainly says,  
“Religious suffering is at one and the same time the expression of real suffering and a  
protest against real suffering.”20 This is to say that the need for religion is conditioned  
upon the fact that human suffering (through systematic economic disparity) prevails and  
through the a misdirection of protest. The distressed society finds falty and unreal  
emancipation through religion, according to Marx. Human flourishing cannot occur  
through self-willed determination if it’s suffering is handled through abstract and non-  
empirical means, i.e., religion. As will be further elaborated, Marx’s critique of the  
Hegelian idea of religion is axiomatic to the tenets set out in his thought.  
Another prominent influence to the development of Marx is Ludwig Feaurbach.  
Feaurbach, a critic of Hegel, specifically with regard to conceptions of God and religion,  
develops a humanistic perspective on religion. In one of his most prominent works,  
Essence of Christianity, Feaurbach makes a key distinction about (the Christian) God  
contra Hegel. Hegel’s idea of God--according to Feaurbach (what he calls “speculative  
20 Marx, Critique of the Philosophy of Right, introduction  
7
conception”)--holds that God is ultimate self-consciousness, an absolute kind of subject  
that is necessitated by the process of sublation. Feaurbach, however challenges the  
Hegelian notion that it is possible for an absolute subject to exist without the  
dependency of the object--in this case human beings.21 He argues that it is not possible  
for God “if he is to exist for us, to be an object to us— he must necessarily be  
thought.”22 For Feuerbach, a human being’s mind is an indispensible, and therefore,  
fundamental source, of the idea of God.23  
“Religion is the dream of the human mind,” Feuerbach says plainly in the preface  
of his novel work.24 While this terse statement may summarize the conclusions of the  
Hegelian critic, by itself, it does not completely satisfy the breadth of his claims. The  
essential trait which stands to contrast Hegel is that religion and the idea of God is  
undeniably bound to the empirical elements of nature--i.e., humankind and their ideas.  
Similar to Hegel, Feuerbach distinguished two aspects of God: metaphysical (ultimate,  
absolute, highest being) and particular. However he makes a compelling argument that  
the “divine predicates” are inextricably bound to the subject.25 A divine, infinite being, he  
argues, is only so far known as to the knower, in this case humans. One “cannot know  
whether God is something else in himself or for himself than he is for me; what he is to  
me is to me all that he is.”26 It is the fallacy that divine predicates and the subject have  
21 Ludwig Feuerbach, Essence of Christianity, Found in The Fiery Brook (1841), trans by Zawar Hanfi and  
George Eliot, Verso: (New York, NY, 2012), 226  
22 Ibid  
23 There is certainly a case to be made that Feurerbach’s arguments are slightly hasty, as Hegel  
conception of God is complex and nuanced in The Phenomenology. It could be conceived that he, too,  
holds that God exists only through objective consciousness’ conceiving of God.  
24 Feurerbach, Essence of Christianity, xiii  
25 Ibid, 19  
26 Ibid, 16  
8
real distinguishability, that leads to Feurerbach’s coined term “theology as  
anthropology.”27  
The influence of Ferurerbach on Marx, is not easily overstated. As Hook  
mentions, in the early period of Marx’s coming of influence (1841-1845), “he was  
Feurerbachian.”28 It is not difficult to conceive of Feuerbach’s appeal to Marx. He,  
perhaps scandalously, turns the ultimate focus of humankind from outward and  
heavenly, to inward and concrete. The extent to which Feuerbach was successful in  
achieving this end is not without debate, but to have made progress toward this  
direction completely disrupts the fabric of intellectual religious thought of his day. In this  
way he establishes important preconditions on which Marx can expound and critique  
further.  
The major departure of Marx from Feuerbach is quite evident in the short work  
Thesis on Feuerbach. In every major point, Marx concludes that Feuerbach has, on the  
one hand, “resolve[d] the religious essence into the human essence,” but that that  
movement stops short of becoming, “sensuous human activity [and] practice.”29  
Essentially, while Feuerbach has made a significant and momentous development--  
bringing the heavens to earth--he has stopped well short of identifying the true  
development of objective reasoning, thought, et al. Namely, he has not comprehended  
that human beings who are couched in their concrete and social realities, develop  
through “practice”.30 For Marx, the object of focus has been moved but remained caged  
27 Ibid, xi Feuerbach later draws on the second person of the trinity to further the idea of the centrality of  
humankind (see pages 50-58)  
28 Hook, 272  
29 Karl Marx, Thesis of Feurerbach, Found in Marx on Religion, ed by John Raines, (Temple University  
Press, Philadelphia, PA) 2002  
30 ibid  
9
in the sphere of theory and abstraction. Which is why he concludes his critique on the  
note that profound, abstract, even accurate theory, is empty without any real and  
significant change in the world in which those objective beings breathe, eat, and work.31  
Feuerbach, according to Marx, is guilty of sharing with the lot of philosophers hitherto--  
namely, that they are all only theoreticians.  
The final major influential figure I will examine in context of Marx’s ideas of God  
and religion is Bruno Bauer. Marx, referencing Bauer states at the outset of On the  
Jewish Question, “You Jews are egoists if you demand a special emancipation for  
yourselves as Jews. As Germans, you ought to work for the political emancipation of  
Germany, and as human beings, for the emancipation of mankind.”32 For Bauer, the  
crux of the issue with religion--in this case, Judaism--was that it stymied the greater  
cause of political emancipation for the German, the human being. The crux of Bauer’s  
argument is that he believes the modern and true “democractic” state is undermined by  
the nature of the existing “Christian State.” This state (what he calls a “non-state”), by its  
own nature, grants privileges to those who abide by the sacred norms established.33 If,  
according to Bauer, the Jewish people (and other religious sects) cannot relinquish their  
religious commitments, then they, by the nature of a religious commitment, forfeit that  
which is necessary to establish a truly democratic state, safeguarded against the  
internal biases of transcendent and abstract ideals.34  
31 “The philosophers have only interpreted the world, in various ways; the point is to change it.”  
32 Karl Marx, On The Jewish Question, Found in Marx on Religion, ed by John Raines, (Temple  
University Press, Philadelphia, PA) 2002  
33 Ibid  
34 There is little debate about the antisemetic tones of Bauer’s work. Although, as it reads, one assumes  
the Jewish religion is his example, applies across other religions. As he points out that the existing  
“Christian State” is also of pointed concern, as it also holds certain religious and internal priorities that are  
applied to the state at large.  
10  
Marx, along a similarly crafted argument, criticizes Bauer’s justification for  
abolition of religion--albeit with a more elongated and complex case. It is this argument,  
against Bauer, where we begin to see the convergence of Marx’s criticism of “the  
modern state” and the criticism of religion as the seeds unto which Marx springboards  
into a positively crafted theory which became Marxism. Firstly, Marx makes a strong  
case against Bauer arguing that he has constructed an argument that “raises questions  
which are not part of his problem, and he solves problems which leave this question  
unanswered.”35 To elaborte on the first point, Marx conjectures that Bauer is asking  
whether religion (in this case Judaism) is a barrier to establishing “political  
emancipation.” However, according to Marx, this is not the crux of the matter as is  
exemplified by the United States’ constitution that has (at least functionally) established  
a separation of church and state.36 Furthermore, Bauer raises the criticism against both  
the Jewish religion and the Germanic Christian State. To Marx, this confines the issue  
to a “theological one” and does not overcome what is the core of the problem--the  
structure of the state iself.37 On the second point raised against Bauer, Marx claims that  
Bauer has not sufficiently brought clarity on the issue of “emancipation” in general. It is  
here where Marx makes a significant signpost that marks themes of his later work. He  
makes a distinction between “political emancipation” and “human emancipation.” His  
ultimate claim in this regard is that humans can be “unfree” in a political emancipated  
state.38 And, it is further evidenced by humans practicing religion in a “politically  
emancipated state” that signifies an incomplete freedom. And moreover, that religious  
35 Ibid  
36 Ibid  
37 Ibid.  
38 Ibid, “the state can free itself from a restriction without man being really free from this restriction, that  
the state can be a free state without man being a free man.”  
11  
practice, which alienates humans from their concrete realities, actually contributes to the  
continuous of the State.  
It is this argument that sets the stage to fully develop a view of Marx’s complex  
and holistic critique of religion. The context involving his understanding of the modern  
state and the critique of other Young Hegelians converges as Marx begins to explicate  
his own understanding of liberation and economic theory. He takes recourse to  
undermine the modern political establishment and uses religion as the voice against it.  
With the aforementioned context at hand, I will now turn to understanding Marx’s holistic  
critique of religion couched in the larger system. I will explain Marx’s response to  
religion through several of his major works chronologically, and conclude with a  
summary that connects the ideas and thought within those works.  
As has already been discussed, Marx’s work On the Jewish Question, critiques  
Bauer’s own critique of religion by ultimately saying the argument stopped short of  
solving the actual issue human beings face in society. Namely, Marx argues that Bauer  
has presented religion as a barrier to political emancipation, which for Marx, is not the  
equivalent of human emancipation.39 What remains to be discussed further is Marx’s  
own views on religion and the way in which it corresponds to his ideas of human  
emancipation.  
Firstly, what does Marx mean by “human emancipation”? To summarize Marx’s  
criticism of Bauer’s idea of “political emancipation,” he says, “The limitations of political  
emancipation are immediately apparent from the fact that the state can liberate itself  
from a restriction without man himself being truly free of it, that a state can be a free  
39 Marx, On the Jewish Question,  
12  
state without man himself being a free man.”40 Here Marx leads into a second part of his  
work, On the Jewish Question, where he outlines the aspects of the political state,  
which cultivate a dualistic, abstract, and therefore, “individualistic” existence. For Marx,  
the political (democratic) state sustains a negative relationship of humans from other  
humans. It establishes a state that maintains the “rights” of “men,” as “protection”  
against the world and others who may infringe on those rights.41 As Marx describes, this  
is an “egoist” human--a “self sustained monad,” who is “separated from other men and  
the community.”42 He offers an eloquent summary in saying that after the feudal period,  
the “revolution dissolves civil society into its component parts without revolutionizing  
these parts and subjecting them to criticism.”43 Essentially, the political state, while an  
improvement on the previous, leaves humans in internal isolation. Without being as  
explicit (at least in this work) about what a society that transcends the political state  
would be, he alludes to this in using the phrase “species-being,” which aligns with  
Marx’s thesis: that humans are dependent on and determined by their social existence,  
and therefore with one another.  
On the Jewish Question, is largely a work criticizing Bauer’s assessment of  
religion as barring human beings from being freed into political emancipation. However,  
in the second part of this work, Marx offers an understanding of “religion in general”  
contra the particular Jewish faith, as it stands within the democratic and free state. In  
this state religion becomes an aspect of the “individual man” among other aspects of  
that human who composes the civil society. As Marx put it, “the democratic state...  
40 Ibid., 50  
41 Ibid, 60-65  
42 ibid  
43 Ibid, 63  
13  
relegates religion to the level of the other elements of civil society.”44 It is an aspect of a  
person that is “intermediated” by the state. For Marx, religion itself is not caustic--it is a  
symptom of that which is caustic. Namely, religion in this kind of state essentially  
discourages natural social relations in a positive manner. It gives credence to this  
problematic social dualism, where one can worship amoung individuals, but be in the  
least concerned with the fellow congregant’s social wellness. It can make disparate their  
real, concrete empirical life and their abstract and intuitive life. Religion in a democratic-  
political state, is a gauge by which that state can perceive the degree to which it has the  
ability to function as an intermediary to the individuals within it. It is why the United  
States is able to not only have an “emancipated” state, but that that state allows for a  
wellspring of religious flourishing. If one can exercise their interior life without much or  
any regard for their real and empirical circumstances protected by the state, then this  
kind of political establishment is successful. For Marx, lacking the acknowledgement of  
one’s empirical circumstances is at the heart of the issue and the barrier to human  
emacipation.  
Marx’s Critique of Hegel’s Critique of Right, contains one of his most (mis)quoted  
epithets to date: “[Religion] is the opium of the people.”45 The first few paragraphs of this  
work offer some of the most profound expressions of Marx’s understanding of religion.  
Readers may often only understand opium in one way in this epithet, namely, its ability  
to ease pain temporarily—not to cure. However, understand a more full extent of opium  
use at the time, will illuminate a better undrstand of Marx’s use of the term.  
44 Marx, On the Jewish Question, 52  
45 Marx, Hegel’s Critique of Right, 171  
14  
Opium in the 19th century was, to say the least, widely used for medicinal  
purposes. It was used to treat a plethora of ailments and was often used by working  
classes to treat a variety of illness as they often did not have the ability to see doctors.46  
Marx himself used opium to treat his illness in the later part of his life. As widely as  
opium was used, it had a massive capital in the marketplace and was the source of  
immense profit. The natural result of this is that it was often the case that forms of  
medicinal opium were diluted or compromised to sell to the working classes. Therefore,  
while opium, a common and effective pain reliever and general antidote for a variety of  
medicinal purposes, also was at the center of class struggle and the imbalance of  
wealth distribution and corruption.  
In this metaphor, Marx’s more complex and dialectical views on religion come to  
light. Religion as “opium of the people,” is to say that it is at one and the same time a  
relief from suffering, but it is also at the same time temporary and contaminated--it does  
not ultimately cure the issue at hand. When he says that religion is both “protest” and  
“expression” of real suffering, he is articulating that the conditions under which people  
exist, require religion to express and alleviate that suffering.47 But what is known to  
Marx and not the practitioners of religion is that it is also a protest against the need for  
religion. It is to say that the squalid conditions of the working class require a fantastic  
narrative which promises hope, unattainable and unforeseeable in the present life.  
Most importantly, Marx’s critique of religion, especially in the Critique of Hegel’s  
Philosophy of Right, is a critique that redirects his audience to a critique of the economic  
and political structure of society. He writes: “the criticism of heaven turns into the  
46 Andrew Mckinnon, “Reading ‘Opium of the People’: Expression, Protest and Dialectics of Religion,”  
Critical Sociology, University of Aberdeen, 5  
47 Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, 171  
15  
criticism of earth, the criticism of religion into the criticism of law and the criticism of  
theology into the criticism of politics.”48 As Andrew Mckinnon points out, Marx is not  
undermining the “sign,” “heart,” and “soul,” of which religion is the container, he is  
ultimately taking issue with “the conditions that require illusions.”49 Those conditions are  
the situation of the poor, who have little agency in the ability to alter their own liberation  
from distress and poverty. It is only natural for human beings to seek relief from those  
conditions. For Marx, it is problematic that the direction in which this often happens  
leaves the earth, so to speak.50 Yet, if that forcible momentum could be dislodged from  
revolving around the “illusory sun,” its inertia could be harnessed in such a way as to be  
directed toward a new orbit--earthlings and their earth-bound liberation.  
While the “Thesis of Feuerbach” is a short and concise work, it provides readers  
with a deep sense of Marx’s attitude toward Fuerbach, a critic of religion himself and  
what that criticism meant for Marx’s understanding of religion. There is one basic  
common thread that flows throughout this work: “praxis.”51 As already discussed, Marx  
takes issue most prominently with Feauebach regarding the interior and egocentric  
perspective of his anthropomorphic religion. As becomes more evident, Marx sees the  
world as a series of social interactions and this lens provides the most bare perspective  
of society. Which is why throughout this short work Marx is most critical in saying,  
“Feuerbach resolves the religious essence into the human essence. But the human  
48 Ibid, 172  
49 Mckinnon, 17, and Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, 171  
50 Ibid, 171. Marx draws upon an astronomical metaphor where humans project revolving around a sun  
instead of “revolving around themselves.” Here, there is a hint of Feauerbachian critique of religion--  
where humans project outward and imaginary hope. The difference for Marx in his critique is that does  
not see religion itself as the cause and source of human bondage. The abstract solution put forth by other  
Young Hegelians, is not a complete critique or solution. It solves an abstract and empty problem that  
does not “change the world.”  
51 “Concerning Feuerbach 182-184  
16  
essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the  
ensemble of social relations.”52 Where Marx, time and time again, separates himself  
from the other Young Hegelians, especially with regard to religion, is that a criticism of  
religion itself is a retreat to criticizing an empty abstraction. For Marx the reality of  
religion is a byproduct of social conditions, and for it to be resolved or abolished, would  
be only an indication that those social circumstances are such that they do not lend a  
need for religion and illusory happiness, because that happiness is satisfied through  
earth-bound resources.53  
A critical element of this concise work is on Marx’s idea of “practice,” often  
interpreted as “praxis.” As has been covered previously, Marx’s departure from  
Feuerbach, is his inability to completely transcend idealism. He brings down “man’s  
perspective” to the earth (man’s mind), but it still remains an abstraction and  
disconnected from the concrete social situation of humans. “The battles that the [Young  
Hegelians (Feuerbach among them)] fought were sectarian episodes in a common  
religious tradition that they shared with their opponents.”54 For Marx there was a certain  
kind of breaking point in the historical development of philosophy, where theory could  
not adequately render significant change or development.55 For Marx any theory or  
philosophical endeavor is empty, and without substance, if it does not manifest itself into  
a realizable and concrete manner. Praxis, for Marx, is a crucial missing component  
omitted by his predecessors--idealists and materialists alike.  
52 Ibid, 183  
53 Ibid, “  
54 Hook, 282  
55 Marx, Thesis of Feurerbach, 184  
17  
The final work of Marx’s criticism of religion I will lend focus to is “The Social  
Principles of Christianity.” This work stands apart in some respects because it offers a  
more rare glimpse into Marx’s (perhaps personal) vendetta with Christianity itself;  
whereas in prior works, Marx situates religion as a byproduct of a greater oppressive  
system, The State. Nonetheless, in this short sarcastic article, Marx uses parallels and  
allegory to vividly illustrate his perspective on both economic systems and its  
complementary component, Christianity.  
Sarcastically, Marx argues, by its very title, that Christianty has failed to establish  
any kind of liberating or justice-oriented principles.56 He summarizes this in stating that  
“The social principles of Christianity transfer the consistorial councilors’ settlement of all  
infamies to heaven, and thereby justify the continuation of these infamies on earth.”57  
The need for some kind of reduction of the injustices plagued by the working class in  
Prussia, at the time, was without debate. The conditions under which this class lived  
was complete distress. The vindication offered to the working class through “salvation”  
was doubly beneficial to reifying the economic and political status quo. On the one  
hand, those (which were large in number) who lived under these conditions were able to  
shoulder them through a kind of artificial hope outside of the life they lived at present.  
And secondly, the sin-salvation complex would naturally garner support to further give  
justification to the current ruling system.  
In the “Social Principles of Christianity,” Marx appears to directly attack religion  
itself. But, a more careful reading will show that Marx is continuing his critique against  
56 Marx, “Social Principles of Christianity,” Found in Marx on Religion, ed by John Raines, (Temple  
University Press, Philadelphia, PA) 2002, 185  
57 Ibid  
18  
the focus on the abstract. For Marx, Christianity “writes blank checks from God.”58 Tying  
the economic and religious criticism into one, there is simply no concrete, empirical or  
real change taking place under Christanity. A blank check from heaven, to Marx, is  
“null.” It is bare, empty, nothingness, that does not change the circumstances of those  
oppressed. To couch Marx’s criticism of Christanity more accurately, it is important to  
note that any system which further propagates abstraction--and therefore complacency  
within a hegemonic social class system--is of the same ilk and same criticism. While  
Christianty has different metaphors and narratives, according to Marx, it’s another cog  
in the piston of unjust capitalism.  
The most important, misconceived, and novel ideas about religion in Marx is that  
he criticises religion from within it’s core, and not directly head-on.59 More specifically,  
as has been duly noted, Marx believed that religion is a by-product, bolstered by the  
unequal social circumstances of various classes. As referenced in On the Jewish  
Question, Marx does not believe that Buauer’s case for abolishing religion leads to a  
true kind of emancipation. He conjects that Bauer’s argument fails to remain critical  
because in a “fully developed” political state (e.g., the United States), the “Jewish  
Question” is no longer a theological criticism, it is a criticism of the state itself.60 In other  
words, Marx indirectly approves of the development of the political formation of the  
modern state from the feudal structure of society, where tenets of theology are not  
directly related to the state. Since Bauer’s argument is essentially a theological one, it  
58 Ibid  
59 In “Social Principles of Christianity” Marx does potentially criticize the tenets of Christanity itself, but  
does so with subtle sarcasm. Even in this short work, he combines both a direct criticism with a more  
serious tone against the ails which bring religion about in the first place.  
60 Marx, On the Jewish Question, 49  
19  
does not go beyond what the political state has already successfully established,  
namely a separation between theology and political affairs.  
The crux of Marx’s criticism against religion is that it (uncoincidentally) is aligned  
well into the fold of “German Philosophy,” which descends from Heaven to Earth.61 For  
Marx, the most important part of philosophy--and that which is hampered by religion--is  
that “man is met in the flesh,” and not from what “[they] say, imagine or conceive.”62  
Religion is the pillar on which dualism stands, and it is that dualism, enacted and  
weaponized by the state, that ultimately prevents real, concrete change and  
development in the world.63 Religion, for Marx--the “aroma of the state”--is that which  
best illustrates the perverted practice of all who believe the status quo is ordinary and  
without criticism. It is the escape and hope for workers who are malnourished and  
maltreated (diluted optimum, as it were), and the weapon of consciousness for the  
owners who prey on the workers for bigger and wider profits.64  
Why, then, does religion not only exist, but thrive? As Marx cites, in democratic  
states “religiosity is par excellence.”65 To answer this, he offers a very obfuscated but  
important paragraph in the “On the Jewish Question.” Those who exist in the democratic  
state, do so in such a way that they are liberated and free “through the medium of the  
state.”66 That is, while they are their concrete and socially situated selves, in a  
democratic state, transfer themselves through the filter of the state, which results in an  
61 Marx, German Ideology, found in Karl Marx and Fredrich Engels Collected Works, Vol I., (Lawrence  
and Wishart Radical Independent Radical Publishers, UK, 1989), 100. Basically, Idealism  
62 ibid  
63 Marx, Thesis of Feuerbach,  
64 This arrangement would explain in the present day, where the middle to upper class have a formal  
casual relationship with religion and those in poverty have a more devoted and committed relationship.  
For the former, it simply is that which enables the continuation of the status quo. For the latter, it is the  
only hope that allows them to endure perpetual distress and hardship.  
65 Marx, On the Jewish Question, 49  
66 Ibid, 50  
20  
abstract and isolated individual diluted of their true “species-being.” In other words,  
human beings, under traditional social contract theory, forfeit certain aspects of who  
they are in order to maintain abstract concepts that establish a state or constitution.67  
The input is pure, social human, the output is abstract, individual civilian. This idea not  
only complements religion (in this case Christianity), according to Marx, it runs exactly  
parallel. In Christianity, he argues, Christ is a mediary to God by which one finds  
salvation and religious liberation. Similarly, humans find political liberation through the  
state.68  
Finally, there is an important, albeit terse note worth mentioning on how a  
religious attitude is framed in Marx. While Marx heavily cirticicized abstractionism, he  
was not against visionary thinking and hope.  
Another important misconception about Marx’s attitude toward religion is  
pinpointing exactly where and what the target of his criticism is. That is, when one  
encounters Marx through a cursory form, there are battle cries to “revolutionize,” and  
“abolish religion!” But, the word abolish specifically used throughout Marx (aufheben) is  
to be understood as a transcending or overcoming, rather than a negative kind of  
removal.69 As Mckinnon mentions, opium had another important trait. It opened the  
mind to a new and illusory vision. These visions, while according to Marx, artificial, were  
nonetheless visions of hope and utopia--heaven. Marx is far from nihilistic. The desire  
and hope for something better is an important specifically human trait. Marx would  
simply argue that to aufenben religion, is to redirect the energy for a better life from  
67 See Hobbes and Rousseau. This is articulated as negative qualities of humans, like the proneness to  
murder, steal and cheat.  
68 Ibid, 50  
69 Mckinnon, 18  
21  
outward and in the future, to inward and at present. When this happens religion will  
evaporate from the minds of those who needed it to survive.  
The question which continues to surface, is whether or not, and to what extent  
Marx’s views were accurate, in this case, specific to religion. The accuracy by which to  
make sound judgments of Marx’s thought would be to note if religion prevails in the  
political state where civil society is distinct from the state. Does the interiority of  
individuals prevail in order to further an unbalanced economy? And, is religion a purely  
internal affair, which contributes to exploitation through the continuous of oppressive  
systems and laws?  
In several respects it would be simple to see that Marx’s novel ideas hold a  
significant and important interpretation of what still exists as a dualistic society reified by  
the democratic state. There is certainly an abundance of material dedicated to an  
economics analysis of Marx. What I will seek to evaluate is the place of religion in the  
democratic state. For Marx, put simply, “the existence of religion is the existence of a  
defect.”70 The source of the defect is with the democratic state promulgating the  
dualistic structure of humans toward each other and themselves. Does religion in a  
democratic state actually indicate the existence of defects and therefore, the economic  
and political reification of the status quo? Does religion satisfy the want of those in  
need, and does it serve as scapegoat to the usury of the wealthy?  
Using three concrete examples in the twentieth century, I will show that this  
perspective is not only incorrect, but inversely true. Religion is an important--even  
essential-- component to the agitation and disruption of the political and economic  
70 Marx, On the Jewish Question, 49  
22  
status quo.71 David Chapell makes a very compelling case that The Civil Rights  
Movement of the 1960s was successful in large part due to the energy and fervor of the  
religious protestors, who were motivated by more than a change of earth-bound laws  
and justice. The development of a New South African constitution, post-apartheid,  
utilized and depended on religious tradition and principles to overcome and reconcile  
the nation together. And finally, the protest against military despotism in Latin America  
was guided and led by Liberation Theology, that brought Marxist ideas together with  
political protest. The last example, even depended on the thought of Marx to form its  
own identity--prioritizing the needs of humans. While the outcome of these movements  
did not resolve the systematic inequities on which they were premised, significant  
change and progress was made.72  
Part 2, Analysis  
David Chappell, in Stone of Hope, at the very least, nuances many accepted  
narratives of the great story that is the Civil Rights Movement. This movement is often  
characterized as a cohesive political protest championed by the progressive majority of  
southern blacks in harmony with liberal, northern whites. However, depicted by  
Chappell, it was actually a political byproduct of “old time” religious revival. It was, in  
fact, religion that fueled the unifying spirit of this movement. Religion was the potent,  
unifying factor that splices through the constructed binary narratives of liberal and  
71 It is important to note, this is not all religion or even the majority of the practitioners of religion. It is very  
well still the case that religion is used to refine the status quo and call into question any protest against it.  
The question here is whether or not, altogether, religion serves an existential purpose of satisfying a  
human defect.  
72 Some may argue against this (see, Alexander, The New Jim Crow), that we have only reformed the  
state of segregation through mass incarceration. However realistic this is, it still holds that laws were  
changed and lives impacted through achievements of this movement.  
23  
conservative. On the one hand, liberals—in all their institutional resistance—had no  
solid foundation on which to springboard any sort of aggressive campaign against the  
inequality promoted in the south.73 However, by this same token, the segregationists  
lacked the same unifying factors. They could not garner a pointed theological or  
ecumenical stance providing the necessary bolstering to sustain segregation.  
Chappell presents a compelling thesis that essentially subverts assumed  
narratives about the Civil Rights Movement. He intensifies the paradoxes and ironies  
through his pointed language, describing the ‘old time religion’ as “irrational,” and  
“supernatural,” albeit pragmatic and useful. This religious proclivity, inherited from the  
prophets and apostles, injected protestors with an “apocalyptic” vision, in which their  
demonstrations went beyond sheer political protest and a call for change. They saw  
themselves simultaneously participating in an earthly and cosmic justice. The protestors  
who inherited the prophetic religion of scripture understood, as did Reinhold Niebuhr  
and Martin Luther King Jr., the essential disposition of humankind. As Chappell notes, a  
large measure of the cohesion within the movement was due to King’s understanding of  
human nature as redacted from Niebuhr. Niebuhr and King, essentially saw power as  
corrupt, and therefore, understood political change to come only through “coercion.”  
Hence, the Civil Rights Movement, by this religious and theological foundation, could  
not resort or be reduced to participating in the political discourses of reason. That’s what  
created hegemonic Jim Crow in the first place!  
King’s attitude toward social reform and justice collided with his theological  
proclivity, as most notably referenced in his essay on Jeremiah, “The Significant  
73 David L. Chappell, A Stone of Hope: Prophetic Religion and the Death of Jim Crow (Chapel Hill:  
University of North Carolina Press, 2004; paperback, 2005),  
24  
Contributions of Jeremiah to Religious Thought”. In this essay King hails Jeremiah as  
rejected and isolated from society because of this strong and righteous devotion to  
Yahweh.74 And that this devotion included an poignant criticism of “idolatry” committed  
by the Nation of Israel. Jeremiah preached a return to justice and purity of society. To  
King this amounted to “religion” disrupting the “status quo” of society. Religion’s “worst  
disservice” he argues is to be “sponsors and supports” of the status quo.75 Jeremiah  
was an example of what King and other civil rights activists believed was an archetypal  
prophet, demonstrating not only justice-oriented outcomes for people, but, more  
importantly, a complete devotion and obedience to God.  
As mentioned, King’s ultimate views of theology, but specifically his attitude  
toward humanity, were largely influenced by Reinhold Niebuhr, who developed what  
King adopted as “Prophetic Religion.”76 This proclivity developed out of--and in many  
respects, stood above--the contexts of neo-orthodoxy and liberalism. King, like Niebuhr,  
had a pessimistic view of humanity, in that he believed humans required a salvific  
moment to reconcile “sin.”77 At the same time, King adamantly resisted a kind of ideal  
humanism, which had proven unfruitful in the present crisis.78 This is further  
emphasized through King’s opposition to J. H. Jackson, who opposed King’s method of  
protest, and was keen to work out black equality through the liberal project of discourse  
74 Martin Luther King Jr. “The Significant Contributions to Jeremiah to Religious Thought,” published in  
The Papers of Martin Luther King, Jr. Volume I: Called to Serve, 1948. Stanford University.  
thought)  
75 Ibid, King in his conclusion remarks that religion has at its worst simply been a reflection of the state  
(as was the case for Israel during the time of Jeremiah). But a true kind of religion is a disruptor to that  
status quo.  
76 Chappell  
77 Martin Luther King Jr. “The Theology of Reinhold Niebuhr,” published in The Papers of Martin Luther  
King, Jr. Volume I: Called to Serve, 1948. Stnadford University (https://kinginstitute.stanford.edu/king-  
papers/documents/significant-contributions-jeremiah-religious-thought)  
78 Ibid  
25  
and ultimate trust in the foundation of the Constitution and politics.79 Yet, Jackson hailed  
democracy and post-war unity as the better way to achieve a desired outcome. His  
point was that “This fight [for civil rights] is more important to America as a nation than it  
is to us as a race.”80 Essentially, Jackson endorsed the achievement of democracy as  
that through which equity would be realized.  
Through this lens, it is clear to see how King as a leader in the Civil Rights  
Movement and as an ardent Prophet to Christianity held a tension between using the  
forces of human created structures with the transcendent and cosmic powers of justice.  
He was committed to a Niebuhrian theology that required, “a combination of this worldly  
and other-worldly hopes.”81 In other words, King held a certain kind of “dialectical”  
theology which held the temporary earth and eternal heavens together. Humans were  
neither completely forsaken to an empty and destitute position--only passively  
redeemed by the will of a mighty, powerful and removed God--nor rescued by the  
powers of reason and savvy government policy. Christians, according to King, were  
redeemed through salvation and called upon to enact justice, here and now, through an  
eternal covenant which transcends the bounds of corporeality.  
The narrative about religion in the Civil Rights Movement would not be complete  
without mention of the White Southern Church. Common associated imagery includes  
throngs of angry white people jesting black protestors. One may also assume a good  
majority of these antisegregationalists were deeply religious. Chappell challenges this  
79 Wallace Best, “’The Right Achieved and the Wrong Way Conquered’: J.H. Jackson, Martin Luther King,  
Jr., and the Conflict over Civil Rights,” Religion and American Culture16, no. 2 (Summer 2006), 206.  
80 Ibid, 208  
81 Martin Luther King Jr. “The Theology of Reinhold Niebuhr,” published in The Papers of Martin Luther  
King, Jr. Volume I: Called to Serve, 1948, Martin Luther King Jr Research and Education Institute,  
Stanford University.  
26  
notion by noting that one great weakness of the anti-segregationist movement was the  
inability of the church to take an equally combative stance as energetic black protestors.  
Chappell states that “white churches were unwilling to make sacrifices to preserve  
segregation. They loved other things— peace [and] social order—more. They could not  
make defense of segregation the unifying principle of their culture.”82 White churches,  
against misconceived ideas, did not take the necessary active protest for a continuance  
of segregation, like their adamant political counterparts. White Christian laypersons  
generally were not outspoken activists who felt that their fervent participation in the  
segregationist movement was an essential part of the faithfulness to God.83 In short, the  
religious activity and energy of the white southern churches to back the segregationist  
agenda was completely outmatched by the prophetic religion and protest of the Black  
churches. Even with a minority in numbers, the fervency and passion of the black  
church energized and sustained the Civil Rights Movement.  
A particular reading of Chappell would suggest that God was on the side of the  
minority of Black protestor-revivalists. While both churches--the black and white--were,  
in formal respects, equally “religious,” the black church was active, energetic, motivated,  
and determined. The manifestations of which resulted in fierce and powerful protests  
that were relentless in the demand and fruition of political and social change. The  
source of this “prophetic religion’s” energy and motivation--against the Marxist  
paradigm--came from outside the human source of reason. It was a transcendent belief  
that “love is the most durable power in the world...and the most potent instrument  
82 Chappell, 107  
83 Ibid, 105-129  
27  
available in mankind’s quest for peace and security.”84 King’s theology and philosophy  
combined both transcendent ideas and pragmatic action. He and his followers (at least  
to some degree) believed that to accomplish their goals they could not return hate with  
hate. And in doing so, they were, at the same time, faithfully abiding in the mission of  
their service to God. Implementing this strategy led to a successful endeavor. In this  
specific example, a microcosm to social progress, achieved a degree of what Marx may  
have had in mind for change. But the source and means by which that was achieved,  
was ironically through extraneous, religious ideas.  
Because Communism was a cultural talking point of King’s day, and because  
King himself was a socialist and ‘revolutionist,’ he duly noted his thoughts on Marx and  
Communism in Strength to Love. For King, “the success of communism in the world  
today is due to the failure of Christians to live up to the highest ethical tenets inherent in  
its system.”85 Despite his adamant distinction between Communism and Christianity,  
King was more ambiguous about the ends to which both sought to achieve. The  
essential difference for King was that Communism held its ultimate belief in the state  
and that the means to achieving social and economic equality were vastly at odds.86 But  
it is clear that King and Marx shared a critical view of capitalism’s tendency toward  
exploitation and inequality. Even going so far as to find a similar criticism of the church  
with tendencies to be only “opiate of the people.”87 But perhaps most paralleled is the  
kind of dualism Marx speaks of with regard to religion. Recalling what was previously  
84 King, Strength to Love, (Fortress Press: Minneapolis, MN), 2010, 51  
85 King, “Theology of Reinhold Niebuhr”  
86 King, Strength to Love, 101  
87 Ibid, “Any religion that is concerned with the souls of men and yet is not concern with the economic and  
social conditions that strangle them and social conditions that cripple them is the kind that Marxists  
describe as the ‘opiate of the people.’”  
28  
mentioned, Marx holds that religion in the democratic state, perfects the “egoist man,”  
that exists in a kind of dualistic paradigm, where the interior and exterior life are  
separated. King similarly articulates this attitude with the church at large stating,  
“Christianity is a Sunday activity having no relevance for Monday, and the church is little  
more than a secular social club having a thin veneer of religiosity.”88 Without directly  
articulating his point, it is clear that King, unlike, Marx did not see this as Christianity or  
religion at all.  
On this point is where King’s theology and practice diverge from the theory of  
Marx. Marx insists that religion is a passive and reactive proclivity because of something  
else--namely, the circumstances of capitalism and the detriment and exploitation of  
within its grip. Religion is a secondary effect to the world. For King, there is a clear  
distinction between this kind of passive and reactive religion and the “prophetic religion”  
of Jeremiah the prophet (and Civil Rights protestors). The former is that which is  
practiced by the church at large, but especially white southern churches. For King, this  
is one shy step away from no religious practice at all. The religiosity of which Marx  
speaks is very akin to the white southern bourgeois religion referred to by King.  
Ironically however, in a certain respect, King and Marx would agree that this religion  
carries with it an inauthenticity because of its function as a cog in the engine of the  
state. Similarly, they would agree that a revolution is needed to curb the systematic  
inequality of the state. The central difference is that Marx’s fuel and catalyst for  
accomplishing this is turning inward, and King’s is turning upward. In the end, King and  
the Civil Rights Leaders proved that a transcendent religiosity can fuel a needed change  
in the systematic injustice of a state.  
88 Ibid., 107  
29  
The South African Council of Churches during the late 20th century anti-  
apartheid movement is the second example that will be examined in analyzing Marx’s  
ideas on religion and politics. The role of organized, peaceful, civil disobedience has its  
roots well before the late 20th century. Mahatma Gandhi in the late 19th century led  
several protests against the systematic oppression of the native Indian workers. The  
crux of his protest was initiated by the prohibition from Indians to Transvaal.89  
Eventually Gandhi and participants were arrested for their actions. But taking workers  
away from the work naturally caused a lag in production, specifically in the mines where  
Indian workers labored.90 An important note to this context, is that civil disobedience  
was only sometimes an isolated act of protest. Commonly, though, these acts were  
strategic moves that turned the state on its head, especially with regard to production  
and labor.  
In the middle of the twentieth century, the policy of Apartheid confronted the  
church head on. The Dutch Reformed Church largely comprising the Church Congress,  
supported the Apartheid laws, stating that “Bantu tribes..would experience a happy and  
prosperous future,” through the establishment of these laws.91 No sooner had large  
established churches formally opposed the laws and endorsements from the  
government-tied church organization. However, the point at which church resistance  
and disobedience began to materialize was when a “mixed worship” prohibition  
movement was beginning to form. Churches generally decided to deliberately and  
formally forgo adherence to the law. In one particular instant, Archbishop Clayton had  
cited that he and his congregants would be disobedient to God if they were obedient to  
89 L.D., Hulley, “The Churches Civil Disobedience in South Africa,” Missionalia, April 1993, pages 74-85  
90 Ibid  
91 Ibid  
30  
the law.92 The vehement opposition to such laws led the government to wane the  
attempts to formalize and enforce such laws with fidelity and scale.  
However, the most predominant instances in which the church was a catalyst for  
organized resistance and disruption came in the 1980s. Derrick K. Hudson-Allision  
makes a compelling case that a two-fold strategy led to successful protest, and  
eventually change in government. The first being a mobilized black labor force  
disengaging from economic production, which stymied the South African economy.  
Secondly, Hudson-Allison attributes the sustenance of this labor movement through a  
faith-infused “prophetic expression.”93 The two strategies together, he claims, ultimately  
pushed the existing government to fold.  
While obvious, to some degree, it should not go without noting that the Dutch  
Reformed Church was a major--if not necessary--ally in the apartheid government.  
However, church endorsed and sanctioned oppressive regimes have always existed.94  
According to the work of Charles Villa Vicencio, two distinct Western Christian traditions  
exist--at least in its relationship to politics and the state. The “dominant” tradition,  
according to Villa-Vicencio, aligns itself to the state and “will not challenge it, unless all  
other options are exhausted.”95 Naturally, the church has found itself actively, or  
passively supporting oppressive regimes.96 The other theological framework is the  
“alternative tradition,” which is marked by unwavering advocacy of the poor and  
oppressed. The tradition of the South African Council of Churches (SACC) was fueled  
92 Ibid., 78  
93 Derick K Hudson-Allison, “The Role of Non-Violent Resistance in South Africa: Black Labor Movements  
and the Prophetic Church in the Spiral of the Apartheid State, 1980-1989,” Princeton University, 2010  
94 Ibid., not long after the birth of Christianity Constantine made it an official state religion.  
95 Ibid., 191  
96 Villa Vencio’s work largely focused on the Latin American church and regimes  
31  
by this “alternative tradition,” seeking to dispel an oppressive government regime  
through civil disobedience and organized resistance tactics.  
Before surveying some of the concrete examples of how the black labor force  
and the SACC collaborated to achieve successful regime change, there’s an important  
point to consider in context of this larger work. There is a clear common outcome  
desired by both the Marxist and a Civil Rights activist (among other activists in this  
case); namely, the revolution of government to change laws and systems that  
systematically oppress the poor and disenfranchised. For Marx, this manifests in a  
violent overthrow of the bourgeois.”97 A recognition of egregious oppression and  
exploitation of labor, the proletariat removes the bourgeois ruling class through force--  
much in the same way were held in their position. Through a revolution supported and  
energized by the church, this takes on a different form. Though often termed “non-  
violent,” and while the SACC did not endorse and support armed resistance, the  
resistance was a forceful disruption and agitation to the state. But prior to the 1980s,  
this was not the case. The militant branch of the African National Congress (ANC) had  
for thirty years prior engaged in violent tactics in an effort to secure rights and equality  
for blacks in South Africa.98 Eventually however, the ANC had come to recognize the  
inability for this kind of movement to find success.99 Out of this recognition was born an  
organized movement to non-violent resistance, which was “sustained” by the Council of  
Churches.  
97 Karl Marx and Fredrich Engels, “Manifesto of the Communist Party,” Marx/Engels Selected Works, Vol.  
One, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1969, pp. 98-137, ed. Samuel Moore  
98 Hudson-Allison, 192  
99 Ibid., this was in large part due to the terrain, human cost, and lack of singular voice.  
32  
The non-violent and disruptive tactics performed by the working class black  
population were targeted and strategic. One vital and effective non-violent tactic was  
massive boycotts of the black labor force. Because the South African economy was so  
dependent on the labor of blacks, these boycotts severely impacted the manufacturing  
sector in the country. Furthermore, the movement was so ubiquitous and powerful that it  
could not be contained or extinguished by the government.100 Other tactics came into  
direct conflict with the church, coercing it directly into the political arena. Namely,  
conscientious objectors to military service. While the church and church denominations  
were more or less fluid on the role of service to the military, the infringement on the  
“right to religious freedom” in the form of conscientious objection, was generally held as  
an indispensable part of commitment to one’s faith. Similarly, laws prohibiting “mixed  
marriages” brought the church directly into the fold of political conflict. In 1981 the  
Presbyterian Church formally gave ministers authority to break what was, at the time,  
the law of the land.101 While these instances were not of relative significance, they are  
illustrative to the larger movement taking place within the role of the church in the  
dismantling of the apartheid government.  
The SACC and church involvement at large, in the South African Revolution, was  
in part birthed out of the Vatican II Council, which largely emphasized pursuance of  
social justice, economic equality, and an overarching concern for the “poor” and  
disenfranchised.102 The conviction of this council was that the catholic church has a  
responsibility to involve itself in the concrete emancipation and freedom for those  
100 Ibid, according to Hudson-Allison, a nation-wide two-day strike had such an impact on the government,  
that it was a singularly important part of bringing them to the negotiating table.  
101 Hulley 81.  
102 Ibid.  
33  
oppressed.103 Hallmarks of this movement include the longstanding coined theological  
phrase, “preferential option for the poor.” Through this formal declaration, roots were  
formed which established liberation theologies often practiced, but not limited to Latin  
America. Two other formal theological South African influences include the Christian  
Institute, established by reverend Naude of the Dutch Reformed Church and the  
Institute for Contextual Theology. The former was established in an effort to secure  
support from within the Dutch White Church to find the meaning of the gospel to  
advocate on behalf of the poor. Naude’s conviction was that this was to be achieved  
through broader political participation and power granted to the black population in  
South Africa.104 Finally, the Institute for Contextual Theology (ICT) propagated the idea  
that theology was “to be done in real life in the world.”105 In other words, the church and  
theological convictions were most--if not only--meaningful by the ways in which it is  
applied in concrete liberation. The ICT not only retroactively attributed transcendent  
meaning to those fighting the apartheid regime, it fueled the movement up through the  
change of government.  
The SACC, in many ways, served as an important practical and organizational  
pillar on which the non-violent anti-aprtheid movement could lean. The church provided  
shelter and food when people’s homes were demolished in the wake of government  
crack-downs.106 Churches also served as important hubs for organization leaders to  
meet and mobilize their efforts. Furthermore, the church was also a large and visible  
organization that was a government threat simply by the sheer magnitude of its  
103 Allison-Hudson, 196  
104 Ibid., 197  
105 Ibid.  
106 Ibid, 195  
34  
influence. However, more importantly--at least in terms of the broader movement itself--  
the church was the invisible fuel that gave activists the will and energy to carry forth  
their mission. Desmund Tutu, among others, were the manifestation of the church  
inserting itself directly into the political area. In his Nobel Peace Prize acceptance  
speech (but in many other places), Tutu says “When will we learn that human beings  
are of infinite value because they have been created in the image of God, and that it is a  
blasphemy to treat them as if they were less than this and to do so ultimately recoils on  
those who do this?”107 Here, a clear and forceful notion is made that unified the non-  
violent anti-apartheid movement. A transcendent origin of human species reveals that  
unjust and unequal laws cannot be reasonable but also cannot be truly religious--  
something the apartheid government (and other governments, past and present) had  
needed to justify.  
Subsequently, church leaders became the direct targets of government and the  
martyrs of the movement.108 The ensuing actions only further mobilized and energized  
non-violent resistance against the government. The largest peace protest for several  
decades was led by church leaders shortly thereafter. And finally, less than two years  
later, the government began negotiations with the ANC, which led a government regime  
change in 1994.  
Hudson-Allison makes a strong case that even though concrete economic  
circumstances give rise to, and are often ameliorate socio-political conflict, “materialistic  
107 Desmund Tutu, “Nobel Lecture,” December 11, 1984, found at  
<https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/peace/1984/tutu/lecture/>  
108 Hudson-Allison, 200. Most notably, on February 29th, 1988, the Apartheid government arrested  
several church clergy after a service, purportedly for igniting actions against it.  
35  
determinism often slights nonmaterial motivations.”109 It is evident that the church at  
large in the South African Revolution was an essential component to the continuance of  
a successful, impactful, and longstanding protest against the government. Hudson-  
Allison notes that the three essential functions the church played in this way include:  
“institutional stability and moral authority, capacity for empowering individuals to act,  
and a commitment to non-violence.”110 The church acting as an important agent for how  
protest should be conducted provided an overarching ethic, which enabled the church to  
curtail violent resistances, for instance. Because the church is an intermediary to the  
transcendent, it provided the opportunity for activists to engage in activities that were  
not necessarily dependent on a certain outcome. If one was protesting in obedience to  
God and to the cause for justice, then the outcome was of secondary importance. This  
kind of motivating tactic enabled relentless efforts. And finally, the church maintained a  
commitment to non-violent strategies, which paralyzed the government from fighting  
against it with the forceful justification it could have, should it have been threatened with  
force. These together made the SACC a vital piece to the revolution.  
The final and most relevant example to be explicated and analyzed is the  
Liberation Theology movement, most notable in Latin America. The reason this example  
is the most relevant is because this movement--uncoincidentally taking place during the  
Cold War--finds direct influence, even correlation, with Marxism. Here Latin American  
theologians make a strong convergence of Marx’s social critique and theology. The  
outcome is a Theology of Liberation.111 In this section I will diverge to examine, more  
109 Ibid., 201  
110 Ibid  
111 Often more descriptively described as a Theology of the Political  
36  
abstractly, just how these two discourses are correlated. Boff’s work is especially  
signicant in context of the other two examples by the nature of the endeavor.  
The intent of Boff’s project is to more-or-less, provide a systematic voice to the  
work of Liberation that has been taking place. He seeks to provide an epistemological  
backbone to the work taking place among active theologies. To put it in his terms, he  
sets off to “capture theology of the political’s ‘material substance.’”112 Theology’s turn to  
the social sciences is abruptly necessitated by the brute fact of human beings’ location  
in concrete reality, determined by historical situation and circumstance--a Marxist  
axiom. Jon Sobrino would describe this phenomenon as the “awaking from the sleep of  
inhumanity.”113 Sobrino parallels this theological movement in the same way Kant’s  
famous work, Critique of Pure Reason, awoke humanity from the slumber of  
dogmatism. In the same fashion, in a post-Marxian era, knowledge in general--theology  
especially--cannot overlook the realities of the human situation in the world. Moreover,  
that Christians themselves find concerning the concrete realities that directly affect the  
“ontic potential” of human beings further necessitates a need for theology to enfold the  
social situation into itself.114 However, this must be carefully, systematically, and  
methodologically done so that theology can operate in concrete reality but also sustain  
intellectual integrity. In this sense, Boff turns to the social sciences, which have already  
done heavy lifting in terms of effectively articulating the human situation in the world.  
Boff takes measure to warn against a theology that omits a mediated dynamic  
between theology and the political. The theology of this kind he names as “empty  
112 Clodovis Boff, Theology and Praxis: Epistemological Foundations,” trans. Robert Barr, (Maryknoll, NY:  
Orbis Books, 1987)  
113  
Jon Sobrino, The Principle of Mercy: Taking the Crucified People from the Cross (Orbis, 1994)  
114 Boff  
37  
theorism.” It’s a theology that produces an “overabundance of signification for its own  
sake.” It blatantly ignores the “scandal” of the poor and oppressed.115 Elsa Tamez  
provides an important example of how this theological tendency operates from a biblical  
standpoint. She argues that the common “justification by grace through faith,” should  
not be understood from an abstract notion of sin, but one enriched by the context of the  
time it was written and also contextualized for people now in the same way. She argues  
that the poor who first read this would not have understood the abstract notion of sin in  
the first place. Therefore, it is not only more theologically sound to apply this concretely  
than abstractly, but also more relevant. The sinner’s guilt relief is not enough to address  
the manifestation of Latin America’s “structural sin,” that which is an egregious offense  
to God, according to Tamez.116  
Boff strongly contends that speculative theology (and philosophy) is outright  
anachronistic. The emergence of the social sciences—which is ultimately a  
conscientious, introspective observance of society itself—gives name and voice to a  
social problem. For theology to regain a relevant and viable discourse, it, according to  
Boff, needs to, in one sense, envelop Marx’s critique of religion and in another sense,  
circumvent what Marx implies is an intrinsic determination of religion (in this case,  
theology). This critique of religion and theology, more specifically, is relevant to Boff’s  
project because in a strong sense, Marx and Boff have similar critiques. The difference  
is that Boff seeks to rescue theology from its irrelevant tendencies to ignore concrete  
problems of reality, where Marx holds that theology’s implicit motive is to mystify the  
115 Ibid., 8-9  
116 Elsa Tamez, The Amnesty of Grace: Justification by Faith from a Latin American Perspective  
(Abingdon, 1996)  
38  
problems of reality in order to sustain the status quo of class power.117 Muller mentions  
that liberation theology assumes an aspect of Marxian analysis of the human situation in  
the sense that the human being is directly and absolutely conjoined to the historical  
situation in which they exist. Theory is an attempt to retain the status quo through  
abstractionism.118 As mentioned in Part I, Marx claims that theology has an “inverted”  
view of the world by approaching ultimate problems from a top-down, abstract and  
mystical realm, rather than from the concrete situation people faced every day.119  
Boff’s response to this critique is dynamic, or more particularly, dialectical. He  
understands the Marxian critique presenting social science with two conflicting realms:  
one based on empiricism (concerned with truth) and the other idealistic (concerned with  
justice).120 Theology of the political, as one that involves and revolves around praxis,  
must encompass both realms. He names these distinct, but important facets  
“autonomous” and “dependent.” Theology of the Political must operate autonomously in  
the sense that it abides by its law, vernacular, and rules. Its proper object is a  
“theoretical God;” one contemplated by theologians. Nonetheless, Theology of the  
Political subsumes the material rendered by the social sciences. The “believing”  
Christian is a historical being, situated in society, and therefore must find its material  
object there, too.121 This kind of theology, to claim any sort of intellectual integrity, and  
to be ‘pertinent’, needs to be active—it needs to be “full throttle, dialectic.”122  
117 This was ultimately the central view adopted by Liberation Theologies across the globe, which were  
heavily influenced by Marxist thought.  
118 Gustavo Gutierrez, On the Side of the Poor, (Orbis Books: New York, NY), 2015, 65-66  
119 Marx, Hegel’s Philosophy of Right  
120 Ibid, Introduction, “Religion is the general theory of that world, its logic in a popular form, its  
spiritualistic point d’honneur, its enthusiasm, its moral sanction, its solemn complement, its universal  
source of consolation and justicaition.”  
121 Boff, 15  
122 Ibid., 17  
39  
If, according to Boff, Theology of the Political will exist, it must consider and  
consult the sciences of the social, not simply ‘the social.’ In other words, Boff clarifies  
why exactly Theology of the Political is to assume a dialectical character rather than  
operate singularly on it’s own terms.123 His primary response, here, is that there is no  
unmediated science.124 Theology, according to Boff, does not have at its disposal the  
ability to ascertain the “real” as given—what is metaphysically speaking, a divine  
purview. To elucidate this point, Boff constructs various “degrees” of knowledge of the  
real. The first consists of the divine purview just mentioned, where the real is simply  
given and seen directly. One degree of knowledge is the “common sense” or everyday  
kind of knowledge of the real. The third degree is where the sciences of the social  
dissect and extrapolate information of the social not immediately known. The fourth  
degree of knowledge is the activity (praxis) of the theology of the political.125  
Theology cannot see itself as having direct access to the empirically ‘real’ or  
suspend itself as having a totalizing discourse. Therefore, it must rely on social analysis  
to provide it with “raw material.” This manifests in a “constitutive” relationship between  
theology and the social sciences. While first theology, according to Boff, can maintain  
an “application” based relationship to the social sciences—that is, a relationship where  
each respective discipline operates independent of the other—a second theology is  
constitutive. It functions as interplay, where each exchanges terms and value to the  
other.126 Theology of the Political—by its own name—bears this kind of relationship:  
Theology of the Political.  
123 On this point is primarily where Liberation Theology will diverge from Marx  
124 Ibid., 21  
125 Ibid., 23  
126 Ibid., 30  
40  
Moreover, in Chapter Two Boff makes clear that theology’s character is one that  
is active, dynamic and fluid. The constitutive relationship between the political and  
theology demonstrates that theology is itself a “labor of production.” Second theology  
subsumes the objects of its inquiry and turns them theological, what Boff calls  
theology’s “second voice.”127 This point of Boff’s is imperative in making an  
epistemological claim. If theology is itself a movement, its epistemological nature  
changes. It is also notable that this bolsters theology’s intellectual and academic status  
as a science, albeit, a different type of science. The true epistemological aim of this  
work is to give systematic articulation of what has been a common thread in liberation  
theologies hitherto. Gutierrez specifies that the divine salvation story—which was  
practiced in the early church and has since lost its way—is reduced when it is not  
considered as a part of the unfolding of history. A “guaranteeing of heaven” is not a  
complete picture of God’s salvation.128 Boff’s project is to nuance and structure these  
tenets articulated among many Liberation Theology scholars.  
Having established the dynamic relationship between Theology of the Political  
and the social sciences, Boff fends off an important and double-sided objection, namely,  
the “idealization of faith.” One side of this objection claims that theology, when  
performed and practiced in the concrete world of the real, can reduce itself to political  
ideologies, void of the divine transcendent aspect. On the other side of this objection,  
however, is a potential danger of contemplative faith (first theology) to obsess itself with  
“transcendent” ideas, thus bracketing itself from the real world.129 Boff’s response to the  
127 Ibid., 32  
128 Gustavo Gutierrez, A Theology of Liberation, (Orbis Books: New York, NY), 1988. Gutierrez, here,  
both articulates and rebuttals the Marxist claim against theology.  
129 Boff, 39  
41  
objection and danger is in line with his dialectical approach hitherto. Theology of the  
Political must, by definition, attend to the transcendent while simultaneously recognizing  
that its operative objects (human beings) are themselves situated in a concrete reality.  
For Boff, to present a sound epistemological theology, both a first and second theology  
need to work in tandem. One cannot replace the other, neither can one supersede or  
impose itself over the other. The danger of doing so—as has been the accusation  
against Liberation Theology, for example—can lead to the “ideolization of the faith.”  
Equally dangerous, is the already iterated Marxian critique of theology (first theology),  
which alienates the world’s concrete problems through abstraction. As Boff says,  
“theology of the political respectsthe transcendence of faith only to the extent that  
it[acknowledges] its particularity according to the particularity of its historical  
condition.”130  
But still, theology seems to carry with it an “absolute” or ultimate element  
intrinsically connected to its work. Again, Boff makes clear that in its dialectical nature,  
Theology of the Political operates “practically” and “theoretically,” or in this case in the  
essence of faith and the existence of faith.131 In a Hegelian sense, Boff does not see the  
various binaries of Theology of the Political in opposition. In this system (at least), they  
work cohesively. The absolute and abstract (essence) elements of faith express  
themselves in the concrete reality (existence) of faith. In reference to the question of  
theology’s ‘absolute’ scope, Boff takes the following stance: “Theology is not absolute  
discourse. It is discourse of the Absolute.”132 Theology, as such, working in reality,  
130  
Ibid., 40  
131 Ibid., 45  
132 Ibid., 46 This same theme is mentioned in Sobrino’s Jesus in Latin America. He argues that a  
contemplation and focus of Christ as the “historical Jesus is not a reduction, but rather a more accurate  
42  
extracts the limited concrete material and opens it to a vertical transcendent reality. This  
is how Boff adequately clarifies the objection stated above and how he refers to  
Theology of the Political as a “regional discourse” and universal discourse.”133  
The final chapter of Part I, Boff seeks to clearly and distinctly mark the  
boundaries of social sciences and theological discourse. Issuing the limitations and  
distinct confines of social scientific inquiry is one of two important facets of the  
discussion of the social-analytic mediation. In so doing, he allows each respective  
discourse to have its say, but only within the limits it ought to be producing conclusive  
statements. Only after establishing the precincts of sciences, can that given science be  
considered in total. In other words, science can be utilized by theology when  
theologians know science’s limitations. Respectively, theologians can perform their  
tasks without infringing on other disciplines by claiming absolute dominion within the  
nature of the discourse. The theologian’s positive task is to pronounce a method for the  
concrete human being to connect to a universal and absolute transcendence. In this  
final chapter of Part II, Boff articulates this important relationship.  
To conclude a summary of Part I of Boff’s work, it will be worth noting an  
important aspect of the human being with regard to Liberation Theology. Echoing Marx,  
Liberation Theology reworks the ontology of the human being from a theological  
perspective. Nowhere is this reworking taken more seriously than in Sobino’s Principal  
of Mercy. Sobrino makes the strong case that “mercy” is at the heart of God’s proclivity  
and appropriate portrayal of Chris as the access point to God, considering some-thing or some-one is the  
contemplator. In Sobrino’s words, “[The historical Jesus] shows the emphasis of liberation christology on  
the notion that in Jesus there has appeared both God’s descent to human beings and the manner of the  
human being’s access to God.” Jon Sobrino, Jesus in Latin America (Orbis Book: New York, NY, 1987),  
16  
133 Ibid, 47  
43  
to humankind and, thus, should be mimicked by the Catholic Church.134 Ensuring that  
human beings are able to fulfill their ontic potential is and should be the mission of the  
church. When Jesus was asked how one is to fulfill the greatest commandment, says  
Sobrino, he tells them the story of a man who has pity and “re-acts” to that suffering of  
another.135 The realization of what Sobrino calls “the total human being,” is the essential  
mission of the Christian Church. Sustaining the abstract notions of theology only serves  
to reify systems that “crucify” and propel and produce fragmented human beings.136  
In concretizing the relationship between the social-analytic mediation and  
theology, Boff considers a “code” that this dynamic should abide by. And further, this  
code is governed by the principles of “autonomy” and “anti-dogmatism.”137 The former is  
the positive approach of the sciences, where a given discipline functions by its rules in  
relation to its object. The latter is the negative, or cautioned aspect, where the  
disciplines can speak of conclusions confined to their circles of domain. Penetrating the  
limits of a discipline’s confines breaches the integrity of knowledge and epistemology.  
The example Boff provides, in relation to theology, is that of deus ex machina: that  
theology should avoid making the case for scientific miracles because it does not align  
with the conclusions of modern scientific discourse, and because science lies outside of  
theology’s scope.138 This does not mean, however, that theology is stymied, or stopped  
in its tracks. To Boff’s point exactly, theology’s labor of production, reorganizes itself—in  
this particular case, “demythologizes”—so that it can provide positive and important  
134 Sobrino, Principal of Mercy, 17-20  
135 Boff, 17  
136 In similar ways discussed in Marx’s work  
137 Ibid., 51  
138 Ibid., 52  
44  
insights to Christian communities within its “regional discourse.” In the Hegelian spirit,  
theology starts when, in some respects, it ends.  
Furthermore, social scientific discourses cannot absolutize their statements  
either. According to Boff, the Marxian critique of the society is legitimate only in one  
sense: it’s “scientific aspect.” It’s philosophical aspect, the “all-explaining”  
Weltanschauung, does not hold according to the code established by Boff.139 More  
specifically, Marx’s critique of society is useful for theologians, political scientists, and  
academic psychology, et al. But, for Marx’s conclusions to find any sort of absolute  
declaration is beyond its scope. Marxism derives its conclusions on the principles that  
are verified in history. But history is a constant development, therefore, not allowing for  
an ultimate claim to be made, because, under this condition, verification is itself,  
ongoing.140  
The ultimate point being that the code for the relationship between the social-  
analytic and Theology of the Political is carefully drawn out by Boff. Its nature is  
dialectical, and its purpose is both to circumscribe and to cultivate. Scientific discourse,  
whether theology or something different, will thrive when it’s function and operation are  
within its particular purview. As Boff duly notes, when theology knows its limits it is a  
sign and signifier of the status of its “epistemological health.”141 He is doctoring a  
plethora of Liberation Theology that’s epistemological foundation is struggling to sink its  
footing. Part of the reason for this will be parsed out in the final section of his work, but  
what makes this an especially difficult task is that Theology of the Political has a moving  
139 Ibid., 56  
140 Marx did argue that history would end if his claims were seriously enacted—perhaps part of his  
solution to the problem stated.  
141 Ibid., 47  
45  
target. Theologians such as Severino Croatto and Leonardo Boff, and others discuss  
Liberation Theology as a movement. Croatto discusses this in terms of biblical studies  
having a dynamic rather than static character.142 Leonardo Boff discusses this same  
phenomenon with regard to the Spirit’s movement through history. That Christianity has  
become attuned to the cries of the poor and to render a theological articulation of  
attending to these cries is the challenge for theologians.143 Clodovis Boff is making the  
most focused attempt in doing just that through the project at hand.  
Conclusion  
In conclusion of this project, I discuss two important points. The first will cover the  
major distinctions between Marx and “Prophetic/Contextual/Liberation Theology.”  
Secondly, I will seek to address points in which Marx and these ‘active’ theologies  
converge. It will become apparent, against common understanding, that Marx and the  
religious activities in these groups had more in common than at first would be apparent.  
One of Marx’s strongest criticisms of religion is with regard to what he calls the  
inverted consciousness. Again, he contends that religion is erected to address real  
problems with transcendent (unreal) solutions, outside of the world.144 He ultimately  
makes a powerful case that theology and God can be a root cause to alienation of  
individuals, most essentially by doubly legitimizing the positions of the oppressors and  
mitigating the revolt of the oppressed by sciphening distress and torment toward airy  
ideas about heaven and redemption. Most prominently mentioned in the “Social  
142 Severino Croatto, Biblical Hermeneutics: Toward a Theory of Reading as the Production of Meaning  
(Orbis Books: New York, NY), 1987  
143 Leonardo Boff, Come, Holy Spirit (Orbis Books: New York, NY), 2015  
144 Marx, Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right  
46  
principles of Christianity,” where he claims that oppressive rulers “transfer....settlement  
of all infamies to heaven, and thereby justify the continuation of these infamies on  
earth.”145 Essentially religion for “eighteen hundred years” has used systematically  
abstracted liberties and rights to life from the oppressed. On the one side, it has used it  
to legitimize its claim and sustain its power, and on the other hand, keep the oppressed  
in their place through heavenly hope.146  
However, even in this major point of divergence, Marx and Liberation Theologies  
both can agree on the point mentioned above. In all three stated examples, each was  
combating a form of religion reifying oppressive systems. In the case of the Civil Rights  
Movement, segregationists appealed to biblical texts to support the separation (and  
ultimately the supremacy of whiteness)147 In South Africa the Dutch Reformed church  
was the central organization purporting the continued “social order” of Aprtheid. And,  
Latin American Liberation Theology’s anthem often cries foul against theology that does  
not act against real-world injustices and oppression. Therefore, in many clear respects  
even on this issue, religion cries foul against a distorted or perverted version of itself.  
In turning to the ways in which Marx and religion converge. The first and perhaps  
most apparent, is the call to achieve liberation/justice in the world. Beyond this general  
commonality, both Marx and these religious movements took specific aim directly at the  
church which came alongside oppressive government powers. As mentioned above,  
segregationists, the Dutch Reformed Church and at times the Catholic Church in Latin  
America, bolstered the justification of the government--and its subsequent tactics to  
145 Marx, “Social Principles of Christianity”  
146 Raines, in his commentary here, offers a qualification regarding sympathies from Marx and Engles on  
religion as a catalyst of protest. In the end, he asks a fair question: “what has religion mostly done?”  
147 The “curse of Ham” was often a reference referred to be slave holders in the 19th century  
47  
secure its grip on power. In modern nation states, according to Marx, the production of  
goods through the abstraction of human labor (disconnectedness of human work from  
the material) is supported by “Protestantism.”148 Marx believed that the American form  
of Christanity was especially suited to support a kind of economic dualism, where mind  
and body were disparate entities. It was against this abstractionism through religion that  
he ultimately criticised.  
Ironically, while Marx’s arguments against religion were themselves quite  
theoretical and abstract, the late 20th century religious movements critiqued religion  
from within with a more intuitive and direct approach. While these movements, without  
question, vehemently critiqued the religious establishments that supported oppressive  
regimes, for the purposes of the projects, it is most important to note that they took  
acute aim at the structure of the system itself--i.e., capitalism. Martin Luther King Jr. did  
not shy away from asserting himself as a socialist economically. In his speech,  
“Pilgrimage to Non-violence,” he says:  
The gospel at its best deals with the whole man, not only his soul but his  
body, not only his spiritual well-being, but his material well-being. Any  
religion that professes to be concerned about the souls of men and is not  
concerned about the slums that damn them, the economic conditions that  
strangle them and the social conditions that cripple them is a spiritually  
moribund religion awaiting burial149  
Similarly, Contextual Theology appeals to the situated human species in the world as an  
intuitive basis to find liberation not only in a transcendent way, but in a real and  
important way on earth.  
148Marx, Capital (1867), in Marx and Religion, ed. John Raines, (Temple University Press: Philadelphia,  
PA), 2002, 195  
149 Martin Luther King Jr, “Pilgrimage to Non-Violence (April 13, 1960),” Research and Education Institute,  
Stanford University,  
48  
Perhaps the most important and overlooked similarity between Marx and  
Prophetic Religion is the role transcendence holds in social liberation and revolution.  
While obvious that this principle exists in the examples stated above, it is important to  
briefly summarize Boff’s work, which provides Liberation Theology a systematic  
backbone, connecting concrete praxis and abstract theology. What Boff essentially  
states is that social science provides the material substance for theology's endeavors.  
In Boff’s words, the practical drives the theoretical; “theory represents practice.”150 The  
dangers of theorism and abstractionism are markley voiced through Boff’s work as well  
as other Liberation Theology writers. Together these opposition voices with Marx, more  
or less claim that omitting the real and concrete distress of people leads to runaway  
theorism--or in Marx’s case abstractionism. A notable difference is that Marx believes  
liberation will render religion obsolete, and Liberation theology holds that liberation will  
fulfill religion.151  
Less obvious is where a transcendent principle exists in Marx’s writings.  
However, there are two points worth noting in Marx that suggests he held to an  
underlying, even abstract, principle. The first is the passage from A Critique of Hegel’s  
Philosophy of Right, in response to Marx’s own hypothetical question: “From where is  
the positive possibility of German emancipation?”152 His answer, as Mckinnon notes, is  
reminiscent of Hegel’s Master-Slave dynamic, and deeply dialectical.153 Marx writes:  
In the formulation of a class with radical chains, a class of civil society  
which is not a class of civil society, an estate which is the dissolution of all  
estates, a sphere which has a universal character by its universal suffering  
150 Boff, 193  
151 King, “A Religion of Doing,” Sermon at Dexter Avenue Baptist Church, Stanford Education and  
Research Institute, July 4th, 1954  
152 Marx, Introduction to A Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right,  
153 Mckinnon, 10-11  
49  
and claims no particular right because no particular wrong, but wrong  
generally, is perpetuated against it; which can invoke no historical, but  
only human, title; which does not stand in any one-sided antithesis to the  
consequences but in all-round antithesis to the premises of German  
statehood; a sphere, finally, which cannot emancipate itself without  
emancipating itself from all other spheres of society and thereby  
emancipating all other spheres of society, which, in a word, is the  
complete loss of man and hence can win itself only through the complete  
re-winning of man.154  
In this passage, “dissolution” [aufhebung] is not to be understood as disregarded or  
eliminated, but rather, in Hegelian terms, transcended--overcome to bring about  
something new. The oppression and “chains” of those referred to by Marx, is discussed  
in the abstract and universal. In large respects the fact of the “chains” opens the  
imagination to a hope and outcomes that not only is without chains, but with something  
more positive and not yet manifest.  
Actively working through suffering and toward realizing something new and  
unimagined, through hope, is an idea closely parallel to the idea of suffering and  
redemption found in the New Testament gospel narratives. The cross represents both  
real and present suffering and redemption together. The symbol of the cross carries  
both the idea of ultimate suffering and death, and salvation and victory over death.155  
Taken in context, this universal suffering and hope fueled a passion for prophetical  
religion and theologies associated with political revolution, understanding both shared  
hope and suffering.  
It is on this principle, found both in Marx and in liberation theology, where Marx  
fails to fully grasp the power and foundation of religion in society. The principle of  
transcendence [aufhebung] discussed in Marx could have found sympathies with  
154 Marx, Introduction to A Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right,  
155 It should not go without mentioning this it also was a political act  
50  
religious movements, and even with religious symbols. Marx adequately provides a  
thorough analysis and explication of religion, which directly and indirectly reifies the  
powers of government. But he (mostly) fails to adequately provide a competing analysis  
for religion that serves as a catalyst to ultimately undo these powers. Certainly, these  
movements do not reach the complete level of “human emancipation” which Marx had  
fully envisioned. They do, however, move the needle further in that direction, in way that  
non-religious movements had  
It is not surprising then, to see Marx and his counterpart, Fredrich Engels find  
sympathies with the early Christians revolutionary character, which unfortunately is  
fragmented.156 Marx’s claims against religion and it’s reinforcement of an oppressive  
state through faulty reasoning are, to a high degree, supported by history and  
contemporary manifestations of religion. However, what goes unaddressed (until  
potentially the very near end of his life) is that while religion does refiy systems, it can  
and does, at the same time, serve as an essential catalyst to social revolutions and  
change. Key to the energy that drives this motivation is described by Marx himself:  
“certainty of victory.” That victory came through the act of participating in the movement  
toward justice, not the outcome itself. It drove protestors to non-violently work and fight  
through a transcendent hope.  
156 There are indications that Fredirich Engels, and Marx--by association--had developed sympathies to  
the early christian movement specifically. Fredrich Engels, “Introduction to Marx’s Class Struggles in  
France (1895),” The Revolutionary Act. Military Insurrection or Political and Economic Action?” translated  
by Henry Kuhn, with an Appendix by Daniel De Leon, (New York News Company: New York, NY), 1922.  
Here he articulates the revolutionary nature of the early Christians against the Roman Empire.  
Furthermore, Marx in a letter to Ferdinand Domela Nieuwenhuis in 1881 wrote that “The dream of the  
imminent destruction of the world inspired the early Christians in their struggle with the Roman world  
empire and gave them a certainty of victory.” Here we can see glimpses of Marx echoing Engle’s  
sympathies for early Christianity’s revolutionary character.  
51  
52  
Bibliography  
Primary  
Boff, Clodovis. Theology and Praxis: Epistemological Foundations. Translated by Robert Barr.  
Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1987.  
Boff, Leonardo. Come, Holy Spirit. Orbis Books: New York, NY, 2015.  
Gutierrez, Gustavo. A Theology of Liberation. Orbis Books: New York, NY. 1988.  
Croatto, Severino. Biblical Hermeneutics: Toward a Theory of Reading as the Production of Meaning.  
Orbis Books: New York, NY, 1987.  
Feuerbach, Ludwig. Essence of Christianity. Found in The Fiery Brook (1841). Translated by Zawar  
Hanfi and George Eliot. Verso: New York, NY, 2012.  
Gutierrez, Gustavo. A Theology of Liberation. Orbis Books: New York, NY. 1988.  
-------------- On the Side of the Poor. Orbis Books: New York, NY. 2015.  
Hegel, Georg. Science of Logic. Found in Lenin’s Collected Works. 4th Edition. Volume 38. Translated  
by Clemence Dutt. Edited by Stewart Smith. Progress Publishers: Moscow, RU, 1976.  
-------------- Phenomenology of Spirit (1807). Harper and Row: New York, NY, 1910. Translated by J.B.  
Bailie.  
King Jr., Martin Luther. Strength to Love. Fortress Press: Minneapolis, MN. 2010.  
-------------- “The Significant Contributions to Jeremiah to Religious Thought.” Published in The Papers  
of Martin Luther King, Jr. Volume I: Called to Serve, 1948. Martin Luther King Jr Research and  
Education Institute. Stanford University.  
-------------- “The Theology of Reinhold Niebuhr.” published in The Papers of Martin Luther King, Jr.  
Volume I: Called to Serve, 1948. Martin Luther King Jr Research and Education Institute.  
Stanford University.  
-------------- “Pilgrimage to Non-Violence (April 13, 1960).” Martin Luther King Jr Research and  
Education Institute. Stanford University.  
-------------- “A Religion of Doing.” Sermon at Dexter Avenue Baptist Church, July 4th, 1954. Martin  
Luther King Jr Research and Education Institute. Stanford University.  
53  
Marx, Karl. Capital (1867), in Marx and Religion. Edited by John Raines. Temple University Press:  
Philadelphia, PA), 2002.  
-------------- Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of the Right, introduction. Translated: Joseph O'Malley.  
Transcribed: Andy Blunden. Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1970.  
-------------- and Fredrich Engels. “Manifesto of the Communist Party.” Marx/Engels Selected Works.  
Volume One. . Edited by Samuel Moore. Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1969  
-------------- German Ideology, found in Karl Marx and Fredrich Engels Collected Works. Volume I,.  
Lawrence and Wishart Radical Independent Radical Publishers, UK, 1989.  
-------------- On The Jewish Question. Found in Marx on Religion. Temple University Press, Philadelphia,  
PA, 2002. Edited by John Raines.  
-------------- “Social Principles of Christianity.” Found in Marx on Religion. Temple University Press,  
Philadelphia, PA, 2002. Edited by John Raines.  
-------------- Thesis of Feurerbach. Found in Marx on Religion. Temple University Press, Philadelphia,  
PA, 2002. Edited by John Raines.  
Sobrino, Jon. Jesus in Latin America. Orbis Book: New York, NY, 1987.  
-------------- The Principle of Mercy: Taking the Crucified People from the Cross. Orbis, 1994.  
Tamez, Elsa. The Amnesty of Grace: Justification by Faith from a Latin American Perspective.  
Abingdon, 1996.  
Tutu, Desmund. “Nobel Lecture.” December 11, 1984.  
Secondary  
Best, Wallace. “’The Right Achieved and the Wrong Way Conquered’: J.H. Jackson, Martin Luther King,  
Jr., and the Conflict over Civil Rights.” Religion and American Culture16, no. 2. (Summer 2006).  
Chappell, David L. A Stone of Hope: Prophetic Religion and the Death of Jim Crow. Chapel Hill:  
University of North Carolina Press, 2004.  
Elster, Jon. An Introduction to Karl Marx. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1986.  
Hook, Sidney. From Hegel to Marx. Humanities Press: New York, NY. 1950.  
54  
-------------- From Hegel to Marx: Studies in the Intellectual Development of Karl Marx. Humanities  
Press: New York, NY, 1950.  
Hudson-Allison, Derick K. “The Role of Non-Violent Resistance in South Africa: Black Labor  
Movements and the Prophetic Church in the Spiral of the Apartheid State, 1980-1989.”  
Princeton University, 2010.  
Hulley, L.D. “The Churches Civil Disobedience in South Africa.” Missionalia. April 1993.  
Leopold, David. The Young Karl Marx. Cambridge University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007.  
Mckinnon, Andrew. “Reading ‘Opium of the People’: Expression, Protest and Dialectics of Religion.”  
Critical Sociology. University of Aberdeen.  
55